Circularity and Begging the Question
Chapter Ten
Philosophy 404
Summer 1999
In making our way to an account of the fallacy of begging the question, we
must attend to two concepts:
The first of these concerns the sentences in an argument: an argument is circular or
not independently of any context. All that matters for the purposes of evaluating an
argument for circularity is whether the conclusion and a premise have the same truth
condition, and this will turn on (a) the syntax of the sentence and (b) its conventional
meaning. The second notion, on the other hand, depends on the circumstances surrounding a
specific argumentative episode, and specifically, on the context within which the argument
is advanced. Note: This distinction between (i) classification of
an argument on the basis of the structure and meaning of its component sentences and (ii)
classification of an argument on the basis of how it is used in a particular situation is
a distinction that runs through this chapter. All the arguments we have looked at can be
identified by their structure and the meanings of their sentences: the slippery slope
arguments, the ad hominem arguments, etc. (Convince yourself of this, if you dare.)
However, whether instances of these argument types qualify as bad or not depends
on the circumstances surrounding their employment. In fact, this is related to a central
theme of this class: that we can analyze and assess arguments from two perspectives -- the
perspective of the thing said, and the perspective of the act of saying.
These notions support distinctions -- circular/non-circular, and
question-begging/non-question-begging -- and these distinctions cut across one another. We
can demonstrate this with a graph. In this graph, I will give examples drawn from Exercise
XXIII in the book. In each case, A is the person who offers the argument and B is the
person who A aims to convince. I will develop these examples in detail below.
Question-Begging | Non-Question-Begging | |
---|---|---|
Circular | (2) A: "Intoxicating beverages should be banned,
because they can make people drunk." -- Context: B knows the identity behind this and disputes the conclusion anyway. |
(15) A: "People with suicidal tendencies are insane,
because they want to kill themselves." -- Context: B doesn't know that a person with suicidal tendencies is a person who wants to kill himself. |
Non-Circular | (12) A: "The drinking age should be lowered to 18,
because 18-year-olds are mature enough to drink." -- Context: B's reason for disputing the conclusion is the same as teh reason for disputing the premise here. |
(5) A: "Gun-control laws are wrong, because they
violate the citizen's right to bear arms." -- Context: Pick your favorite. |
Close Analysis of the Examples: Arguments often contain implicit premises, and
these are no different. Given this, it is useful to write these in standard form so as to
bring out the implicit premises. (Implicit premises: (*).)
(2)
_______________
- Given (a), (b) and (c) have the same truth condition, and so this argument is circular.
- If you know (a) and still have a problem with (c), you will have the same problem with (b).
- Note: This conflicts with the story told on p. 349 in the book, but that story is in error. If you reject the identity between water and H2O, you will have a problem with Susie's argument, but you will not have the same problem with the conclusion as you have with the premises; thus, the argument is not question-begging from that perspective (i.e., Joe's perspective).
(15)
_______________
- Given (a), (b) and (c) have the same truth condition, and so this argument is circular.
- In a situation where you dispute the conclusion but are unaware of the identity given in (a), this argument could be offered to inform you, and so in that context it would not be question-begging.
(12)
_______________
- This is not circular: (e) does not have the same truth condition as any premise.
- If you accept (b), (c), and (d), then any problem you have with (e) is a problem you will have with (a).
(5)
_______________
- (c) does not have the same truth condition as either (a) or (b), so this is not a circular argument.
- No premise is sufficiently similar to (c) such that if you accept the other premises, it would be subject to the same criticisms as (c).
Summary: